The origin of homo sapiens
might seem a question of purely scientific interest, but it is actually
also an intensely political one. From the Just So stories of
evolutionary psychology to various ideas about innate human behaviour,
there are no shortage of arguments seeking to justify aspects of modern
society with reference to the prehistoric past. This is not restricted
to the history of our own species, homo sapiens, as our earlier evolutionary history can also be held to be extremely relevant for understanding the present.
An
example of this was the development of the theory, in the 1950s and
1960s, about the supposedly violent behaviour of an ancient hominid
species called Australopithecus africanus, which was then usually thought to be an ancestor of all later hominid species (the group of species to which homo sapiens belongs). A palaeontologist, Raymond Dart, who discovered various africanus
fossils in southern Africa, believed that he had found evidence of
hunting, murder and cannibalism, and that it was this which had enabled africanus
to give rise to the later hominid species. He called it ‘the predatory
transition from ape to man’, and this was developed in the
popularisation of his theory in the 1960s into the conclusion that
violence was not only innate to modern humans, but that it was in some
way what made us human. The usefulness of this theory to right-wing
arguments against the peace movement was, of course, entirely
coincidental.
The science underpinning this argument for innate human violence was fairly swiftly demolished, with poor old africanus
appearing now to have been more prey than predator. However, this is
not the only instance of perceived hominid history being used to justify
a right-wing view of society. A particular point of contention has been
the question of where homo sapiens first evolved from its
precursor hominid species, and what that means for differences (or not)
between modern human populations; the biological reality of race.
The older theory for the development of homo sapiens
is what is known as the multiregional model. This is based on theories
first developed in the 1930s, reworked by US scientist Carleton Coon in
the 1960s, and picked up in the 1970s and 1980s by a number of
multiregionalists. Broadly, this theory argues that homo sapiens
populations in different parts of the world evolved separately in those
areas. The multiregionalists accepted that earlier hominid species had
evolved in Africa, but argued that once the hominid species called homo erectus had dispersed from Africa about one million years ago, the erectus populations in each area had given rise to their own modern humans. For Europe, the argument was that homo erectus
had arrived from Africa and developed into the Neanderthals, who had
then in turn developed into modern Europeans, but also that modern
humans in other parts of the world would have had a different post-erectus evolutionary history.
This
separate evolution meant that perceived racial differences – in skin
colour, stature, facial features and so on – were real differences
expressing the fact that a million years separated, for example, a
sub-Saharan African and a WASP. In addition, the idea that there were
real different racial groups of modern humans, which had evolved
separately, enabled the multiregionalists to suggest that they might
have evolved at different rates. All were still just about human, but
now some seemed to be more human than others. Carelton Coon even singled
out Australian aboriginies as an example of a group which was less
evolved, just in case anyone could not work out for themselves that it
would not be white Europeans who were thought to have lagged behind in
evolutionary terms.
Some aboriginal groups have tried to turn
this on its head, arguing that their right to the land is strengthened
if they are effectively homo erectus, but the general racist
effect of this theory should be evident. For the multiregionalists, what
was key was that the unavoidable African part of their evolutionary
history was as peripheral, and as long ago, as they could make it. They
could not argue that the evolution of hominids up to homo erectus happened outside Africa, because the weight of evidence was against them, but they could locate their own homo sapiens
origins safely in Europe, via the Neanderthals. They were unable to
believe that anything as impressive as white men could have anything
recently to do with Africa. As Coon argued, ‘If Africa was the cradle of
mankind, it was only an indifferent kindergarten.’
The
alternative theory, developed by Chris Stringer, among others,
throughout his career, is the Out of Africa Theory, or theory of Recent
African Origins (RAO), so renamed because there appears to have been not
one African exodus but several. As the name implies, this theory
contradicts the multiregional model by arguing that homo sapiens
evolved relatively recently in Africa and spread out from there to
become the globally-dispersed species we are today. This theory turns
the idea of the biological reality of race on its head. If we are all so
recently related, it follows that differences in appearance between
populations from different areas must be literally skin deep. Indeed,
work on the DNA of different populations shows that because everyone
whose ancestors were part of the out of Africa dispersal are descended
from a fairly limited gene pool, there is more variation between
different modern population groups within Africa than there is between
groups from anywhere else in the world.
The RAO theory has become
the most generally accepted version of human origins, and presents a
conveniently clear scientific refutation of some unpleasant racist
theories. However, theories of human origins are changing all the time
as new remains are found, or new techniques developed for dating finds
or tracking DNA variations. This new book from Chris Stringer brings us
up to date with recent years of developments, including the startling
discovery of a new hominid species, (although not a human ancestor), the
tiny ‘Hobbit’, homo floriensis. It is a fascinating read, but
from the point of view of the political arguments over human origins
theories, a rather challenging one.
It is always a bad idea to
rest the repudiation of right-wing interpretations of ‘facts’ about the
world on the basis of our own ‘facts’ alone, rather than on disputing
the ideology behind reactionary arguments. Scientific facts are always
subject to new discoveries and can be challenged. The problem with a
broad-brush rendering of the RAO as an answer to racist science, is that
it can imply that it is only the fact of homo sapiens’ recent
evolution in Africa which means that racist arguments about the
superiority of some groups over others are not correct. In other words,
it can appear that if new evidence emerged in support of regional
differences in homo sapiens’ evolution, that would pull the rug
out from underneath our repudiation of scientific justifications for
racism. The challenge presented by Stringer’s new book is that the
nuanced version of the RAO which it presents has had to accommodate some
regional differences. The simple story of African origins told by
summaries of the RAO turns out not to be quite right.
Part of the multiregional hypothesis was that homo sapiens
in Europe was descended from European Neanderthal populations. By
contrast, the RAO held that Neanderthals died out without leaving
descendants, being replaced by the more successful homo sapiens,
either by competition or genocidal violence, depending on how far the
individual commentator was in favour of the ‘nature red in tooth and
claw’ version of human prehistory. However, advances in studies of
Neanderthal DNA now indicate that while homo sapiens clearly did not evolve from Neanderthals in Europe or anywhere else (the evolutionary progenitor of homo sapiens appears to have been homo heidelbergensis, from which both homo sapiens
and Neanderthals evolved), modern Europeans and Asians have DNA which
is closer to Neanderthal DNA than is modern Africans’. This indicates
that modern humans outside Africa may have had some Neanderthal
ancestors. The Neanderthal DNA is about 2%, a reasonably significant
input, which requires explanation in any model of human origins.
Stringer maintains that it is unlikely that this interbreeding happened in Europe, as European homo sapiens
do not appear to have inherited their cold adaptions of light skin,
hair and eyes from the similarly cold-adapted European Neanderthal
populations. The most likely hypothesis, Stringer argues persuasively,
is that homo sapiens leaving Africa encountered people descended from an earlier exodus of homo heidelbergensis into the Middle East. This is not the only evidence of interbreeding between homo sapiens
and other hominid populations. Modern Melanesians, for example, have as
much as 8% DNA which appears to have originated in the Denisovians, a
hominid species also descended from homo heidelbergensis and
closely related to Neanderthals. This is so high a retention of archaic
DNA that Stringer speculates that it may be providing some selective
advantage, such as resistance to endemic diseases.
There is
clearly a danger that these discoveries could be used to resuscitate the
otherwise moribund multiregionalist theory. It is probably not a
coincidence that the multiple authors of a recent paper published in Science on Neanderthal and Denisovian DNA, ‘The shaping of modern human immune systems by multiregional
admixture with archaic humans’ [italics mine]. Stringer however makes
it clear that the RAO theory is amended but not contradicted by these
discoveries of contact between homo sapiens and other hominid species.
In
the first place, Africa retains its importance in human origins, rather
than being pushed aside as in multiregionalist theory. By the last
chapter, it is clear that what we are moving towards is a multiregional
theory of human origins within Africa, with different archaic
populations potentially encountering and breeding with each other over a
long period of time, interspersed with incidences of dispersal out of
Africa. While the theories discussed earlier in the book of how homo sapiens could have bred with Neanderthals and Denisovians remain valid, the point here is that different homo sapiens
populations could have acquired their differing traces of archaic DNA
before they ever left Africa. Regional differences between early homo sapiens
populations could have been due to the accidents of which groups ended
up in which areas, rather than to the archaic populations they
encountered there. It is important also to understand that ancient
regional differences would not be the same as perceived more recent
ones.
Just as important as this reassertion of the importance of
Africa for human origins is Stringer’s consideration of what modernity
means in human evolution. It is easy when thinking about the evolution
of homo sapiens to reduce it to a question of genetics, but
this would be a mistake. Stringer points out that in fact genetic
divisions between species are often not as clear cut as a lay
understanding would have it. The definition of a species in fact is
closer to being groups which in the wild would not breed with each
other, rather than groups which could not successfully breed with each
other even if persuaded to do so by scientists in a lab. In other words,
the definition of a species is behavioural as much as it is genetic,
and for Stringer the evidence for the emergence of modern human
behaviours is as important as that for the development of modern human
bodies.
The evidence for modern behaviours like tool use, use of
symbolic art and burying the dead, which set hominids apart from other
animal species, is patchy, with incidences appearing early in human
pre-history but separated from each other in time and space. Stringer
suggests that this suggestion of patchy cultural development is not an
accident of evidence survival but reflects a reality about how modern
human behaviour developed. His point is that it needs a certain group
size to maintain cultural and technological knowledge over generations,
and a certain degree of contact with other groups to share further
developments.
If small groups become isolated they can lose
important knowledge, as for example seems to have happened to the first
settlers in Tasmania. When they arrived there, about 40,000 years ago,
the island was connected to the Australian mainland, and the settlers
had a variety of tools, clothing and shelters. However, about 14,000
years ago, climatic changes turned Tasmania into an island, and the
now-isolated inhabitants gradually seem to have lost much of their
cultural and technical knowledge, even eventually the knowledge of how
to make fire. Stringer suggests that this may be an illustration of how
culture was developed and lost again many times among different groups
in human prehistory. The key breakthrough for the development of fully
modern human behaviour was not ability to develop this sort of culture,
but the ability to sustain a large enough population to keep it.
It was this, rather than genetic differences, which ultimately made the difference between homo sapiens
and Neanderthals. There is considerable evidence for Neanderthal
culture, including burying the dead, tool-making and decorative
painting, and it seems unlikely that these were simply imitations of homo sapiens’
culture, as has been suggested. The problem for Neanderthals may well
have been that, given the ice-age climate which they had to deal with,
they were never able to develop sufficiently large and connected groups
to maintain and extend these cultural developments. The survival of us,
rather than Neanderthals, may be more to do with the contingent effects
of climate than any innate superiority of homo sapiens’ evolution. As Stringer says, lacking the last Ice Age, it might have been Neanderthals rather than homo sapiens
which survived: ‘Would they have eventually looked back at their own
success, at the benefits of the Eurasian environment, and the problems
of surviving in Africa for their failed relatives, the ones with the
weird foreheads?’ (p.238).
It is reasonable to be concerned that any suggestion that some people today have DNA from non-homo sapiens
hominid species will be interpreted as meaning that some people are
less human than others. However, the lesson of this valuable book is
that these archaic hominid species, if the contingent events which drove
them extinct had worked out differently, would have been different but
actually no less human than us. Engels argued in the Dialectics of Nature
that the essential element in the transition from ape to man was
labour; humans became human because their bipedality freed their hands
to make tools and therefore work to transform their environment.
Stringer’s conclusions seem to lead us back to this insight. That some
of us may have Neanderthal or Denisovian DNA is fascinating for human
history, but tells us nothing about modern regional differences. What
made us human was behaviour, not our genes.
The loss of the basic
RAO theory has taken away the one-sentence simple response to racists
who like to imply that black people are less evolved than they are. In
its place, Stringer has given us a dialectical understanding of our
evolution and what it means to be a modern human, which is ultimately a
much more powerful refutation of the ongoing perversion of the study of
human origins by the right.