Britain joined the war four months before
Bosanquet’s attack on Russell, and politics was unavoidable at the
Aristotelian Society. The Society’s president that year was the Right
Honourable Arthur Balfour, former Conservative prime minister, and a
regular contributor to philosophical journals such as Mind.
Balfour would shortly become Britain’s Foreign Secretary, a position he
held through the remainder of the war. Meanwhile, Russell was already
publicly associated with the push for British neutrality. Just after
returning from Harvard University in the summer of 1914, he set about
gathering the signatures of more than 60 dons at the University of
Cambridge in a letter urging Britain to keep out of the war. Published
on 3 August, the letter constitutes the only known such appeal on the
part of academics.
The UK entered the war the next day. By the end
of the week, the House of Commons passed the Defence of the Realm Act
(DORA), which gave the government broad wartime powers – including
censorship. In 1916, Russell would be dismissed from his post at Trinity
College, Cambridge, following his conviction under DORA (and thanks in
part to a campaign at the university led by another British idealist, J M
E McTaggart). Russell spent six months in jail for his outspoken
pacifism.
Recent historians have criticised analytic philosophy
for disengaging from public affairs during the long 20th century. Some
of its leading exponents, such as W V Quine, have been accused of
cocooning themselves in a methodology they were pleased to call
apolitical, particularly during periods when academics were coming under
attack for purported Leftist sympathies, such as during the Joseph
McCarthy era. One prominent critic (the philosopher John McCumber) has
even suggested that, since anti-German sentiment in Britain during the
First World War resembled in irrational vitriol the anti-communist
sentiment during the McCarthy years in the US, the very founding of
analytic philosophy itself – including in the hands of Russell – was
also tainted with a self-serving political quietism.
But in fact
that gets things almost exactly backwards. Russell’s antiwar protest was
so extensive that it would cost him both his job and, for a time, his
personal freedom. His theoretical antidote to the irrational,
sectarian vitriol between European nations was to try to show how logic
could function as an international language that could be used
impartially and dispassionately to adjudicate disputes. His theoretical
antidote was, in other words, analytic philosophy.
‘The truth, whatever it may be, is the same in England, France, and Germany … it is in its essence neutral’
The contrast with Bosanquet is again instructive. In a passage from Philosophical Theory of the State
that would foreshadow his later attack on Russell, Bosanquet had
decried ‘the idea of a universal language’ which, as ‘a substitute for
national languages, … would mean a dead level of intelligence unsuited
to every actual national mind, the destruction of literature and
poetry.’ Russell didn’t intend logic to become the language of
literature and poetry, much less to destroy those practices. But he very
much intended his ‘scientific’ methodology to destroy a conception of philosophy as an articulation of a ‘national mind’.
The
connection between Russell’s antinationalism and his metaphilosophy
comes out sharply in his political writing of the era. In April 1915, he
was again railing against the role philosophers were playing in
promoting nationalism:
Leibniz, writing to a French
correspondent at a time when France and Hanover were at war, speaks of
‘this war, in which philosophy takes no interest’. … We have travelled
far since those days. In modern times, philosophers, professors and
intellectuals generally undertake willingly to provide their respective
governments with those ingenious distortions and those subtle untruths
by which it is made to appear that all good is on one side and all
wickedness on the other … I cannot but think that the men of learning,
by allowing partiality to colour their thoughts and words, have missed
the opportunity of performing a service to mankind for which their
training should have specially fitted them. The truth, whatever it may
be, is the same in England, France, and Germany, in Russia and in
Austria. It will not adapt itself to national needs: it is in its
essence neutral.
Today, with nationalism recrudescent, we
are in a good position to appreciate that Russell’s insistence on the
neutrality of truth was not mere platitude. Idealists of his time might
not have gone quite so far as to deny truth’s neutrality outright, but
they certainly saw overall philosophical excellence as distinctively
tied to nationality. For Bosanquet and his allies, British idealism
wasn’t just trying to get at the truth. It also aimed to express the
national character of the British people.
Russell has often been
regarded as someone who wanted to rid philosophy of ‘ethics’. But he
advocated banning ‘ethics’ under a specific and narrow description of
that enterprise, one that plainly resonated with his antinationalist
politics. Compare the above quotation from Justice in War-time (1916) with this passage from his more overtly philosophical ‘On Scientific Method in Philosophy’ (1914):
Ethics
is essentially a product of the gregarious instinct, that is to say, of
the instinct to cooperate with those who are to form our own group
against those who belong to other groups. Those who belong to our own
group are good; those who belong to hostile groups are wicked. The ends
which are pursued by our own group are desirable ends, the ends pursued
by hostile groups are nefarious. The subjectivity of this situation is
not apparent to the gregarious animal, which feels that the general
principles of justice are on the side of its own herd. When the animal
has arrived at the dignity of the metaphysician, it invents ethics as
the embodiment of its belief in the justice of its own herd.
Russell
in fact developed his own ethical theories; what he was most dismissive
of was the specific kind of communitarian approach to value advocated
by neo-Hegelians such as Bosanquet, an approach Russell saw as propping
up the nationalist sentiments that had just exploded into a world war.
Idealism
was not the only form of metaphysics that Russell saw as conducive to
nationalism. He also went after the French philosopher Henri Bergson, as well as the Pragmatists
in the US – both familiar targets for him. Russell had attacked Bergson
in a series of talks in the spring of 1913, which were collected with
several replies as a small book around the same time as Our Knowledge.
While Russell was mostly concerned with the details of Bergson’s
metaphysical system, he made his underlying political concerns clear at
the outset. He portrayed Bergson as seeing successful ‘action’ rather
than theoretical ‘understanding’ as the ultimate aim of philosophy, and
this emphasis on action as inevitably leading to ‘imperialism’.
Bergson
would become one of the most important French intellectuals arguing for
military engagement during the Great War. In fact, two weeks after
Bosanquet had condemned Russell’s cosmopolitanism, Bergson gave the
presidential address to the Académie des Sciences Morales et Politiques which was quickly translated and published in English as The Meaning of the War
(1915). Bergson’s bellicosity – in contradistinction from Russell’s
advocacy of British neutrality – is on clear display in these lines from
the book’s opening and closing paragraphs, respectively:
[T]here
are forms of anger which, by a thorough comprehension of their objects,
derive the force to sustain and renew their vigour. Our anger is of
that kind. We have only to detach the inner meaning of this war, and our
horror for those who made it will be increased. Moreover, nothing is
easier. A little history, and a little philosophy, will suffice.
To
the force which feeds only on its own brutality we are opposing that
which seeks outside and above itself a principle of life and renovation.
Whilst the one is gradually spending itself, the other is continually
remaking itself. The one is already wavering, the other abides unshaken.
Have no fear, our force will slay theirs.
Bosanquet’s defenders have often claimed
that it is a misreading to suggest that his theoretical work actually
justifies nationalism, and I don’t know of any evidence that he actively
promoted militarism. But Bergson was extremely vocal in offering
emotional and philosophical pleas in support of allied military action
during the Great War, and in a way that helps make sense of Russell’s
description of some philosophy professors as ‘bloodthirsty’. In February
1917, the French government even sent Bergson to personally lobby the
US president Woodrow Wilson to get the Americans to join the war effort.
The British decision to join the war was a fundamentally different calculation than what France faced
I
do not wish to suggest that Russell had all righteous justice on his
side, and Bergson all wickedness. We do well to remember that France
faced a starkly different set of concerns in entering the war. It shares
an approximately 450-km (280-mile) border with Germany. The British
Isles are and were, of course, insulated by water from such Continental
strife, and to many neutralists the country stood to gain little from
sending soldiers.
But on 3 August 1914, the day that Russell’s
co-signed letter advocating neutrality was published, the British
calculation suddenly became more complicated. The Germans declared war
on France and announced their intention to attack through Belgium, whose
own neutrality had been guaranteed by Britain since the 1839 Treaty of
London. The Germans marched on Belgium the next day, and the British
entered the war in a matter of hours, seeking both to honour the treaty
and to protect Belgian ports that are directly across the English
Channel. So the British decision to join the war was neither irrational
nor unprovoked; but it was a fundamentally different calculation than
what France faced.
Still,
Russell’s continued advocacy of neutralism highlights his tendency to
seek pacifistic solutions even to the most harrowing of international
problems. And this brings us to Pragmatism. Russell criticised the
Pragmatist theory of truth, and often used Pragmatism as a foil for his
own analytic method. But his relationship with the American tradition is
a more complex matter than has generally been appreciated. For one
thing, the distinctive strain of pacifism Russell developed during the
First World War had been directly influenced by William James,
one of Pragmatism’s key architects. Shortly before his death in 1910,
James had delivered two addresses on pacifism that had impressed Russell
greatly, named ‘Remarks at the Peace Banquet’ and ‘The Moral Equivalent
of War’. James’s pacifism was not built on unrealistic optimism, but on
a frank acknowledgement of a very human thirst for violence:
The
plain truth is that people want war. They want it anyhow; for itself;
and apart from each and every possible consequence. It is the final
bouquet of life’s fireworks. The born soldiers want it hot and actual.
The non-combatants want it in the background, and always as an open
possibility, to feed imagination on and keep excitement going.
James
proposed diverting the human passion for violence away from fellow
humans. Instead of conscripting young people into battalions, he
advocated forming an ‘army enlisted against nature’ or something like
what would become a national service corps. Although Russell did not
find this solution fully satisfactory, he would later say in Why Men Fight
(1917) that James’s ‘statement of the problem could not be bettered;
and so far as I know, he is the only writer who has faced the problem
adequately.’
James did not live to see the Great War. But he came
from a family tradition of American progressivism that was very much in
the cosmopolitan, internationalist spirit of Russell’s own ancestral
‘radicalism’, as it has often been called
in the UK. Thirty years Russell’s senior and American by birth, James’s
pacifism grew out of concerns about US expansionism in particular. He
often voiced these concerns in a language of antinationalism that would
have resonated deeply with somebody like Russell. Consider this passage
from James’s ‘Address on the Philippine Question’ (1903) delivered at
the fifth annual meeting of the Anti-Imperialist League in Boston:
Political
virtue does not follow geographical divisions. It follows the eternal
division inside of each country between the more animal and the more
intellectual kind of men, between the tory and the liberal tendencies,
the jingoism and animal instinct that would run things by main force and
brute possession, and the critical conscience that believes in
educational methods and in rational rules of right … The great
international and cosmopolitan liberal party, the party of conscience
and intelligence the world over, has, in short, absorbed us [‘us’ being
anti-imperialists]; and we are only its American section, carrying on
the war against the powers of darkness here, playing our part in the
long, long campaign for truth and fair dealing which must go on in all
the countries of the world until the end of time. Let us cheerfully
settle into our interminable task.
Russell would be in
lockstep with the ‘international and cosmopolitan’ idea that we are on a
‘long campaign for truth and fair dealing … in all the countries’. Thus
James and Russell shared a pacifist cosmopolitanism that stands in
stark contrast with Bosanquet’s grounding of all value inside a
nation-state, and with Bergson’s ‘our-force-will-slay-theirs’
nationalism. It therefore seems unlikely that Russell had James in mind
as one of the ‘bloodthirsty’ ‘pigs’ whose philosophy needed to be
opposed on moralistic ground. Indeed, Russell was forthcoming about his
longstanding admiration for James. Despite their real philosophical
differences, we find Russell writing in the 1940s that ‘among eminent
philosophers, excluding men still alive, the most personally impressive,
to me, was William James.’
‘Two things which are at present increasingly disappearing: loving kindness and scientific impartiality’
Russell was highly critical of James’s book Pragmatism
(1907), but that conflict was something closer to a civil strife.
Russell could not accept that the truth of an idea is a matter of the
idea’s utility (this was his gloss on James’s epistemology). A
despot can make it very useful indeed for subjects to believe that the
Dear Leader is a messenger of God, Russell worried. But it is worth
remembering that Russell highly respected James’s pioneering work in
empirical psychology, and connecting truth with utility was James’s own
attempt to extract philosophical lessons from the best scientific
enquiry. In fact, much like Russell, James often framed his own
Pragmatism in direct opposition with the kind of neo-Hegelian idealism
represented by the likes of Bosanquet.
Here one might charge
Russell with a confusion. His central complaint with Pragmatism is that
the peaceful resolution of disputes depends on the existence of a
rational ‘standard’ that is independent of community opinion, and to
which all can appeal. He thinks Pragmatism seeks such a
standard, but fails philosophically to furnish one (whereas Bergson and
Bosanquet do not even seek an international rationality). As he puts it
elsewhere, ‘impartiality of contemplation is, in the intellectual
sphere, that very same virtue of disinterestedness which, in the sphere
of action, appears as justice and unselfishness’. Pragmatism is not
impartial enough. And yet Russell apparently saw his own philosophical
methodology as anything but politically neutral. He had an impartialist
view of truth – but that commitment is embedded in a broader
metaphilosophy that itself had an antinationalistic agenda, as we have
seen. So how can Russell reconcile his own antinationalistic
metaphilosophy with the idea that the truth must be an impartial matter?
Later in life, as the Second World War was winding down, Russell offered this way of handling the apparent tension:
If
human life is again to become tolerable, mankind must acquire two
things which are at present increasingly disappearing: loving kindness
and scientific impartiality. These two things are inter-connected. At
present, in every country, the schools teach a narrow nationalism and a
view of history quite different from that taught in any other country.
There is no scientific impartiality, and the departures from
impartiality are such as to diminish loving kindness between nations.
Nobody
could reasonably say that either antinationalism or cosmopolitanism is
baked into Anglo-American philosophical methodology anymore. Russell was
a pioneer in showing generations what it might mean to place formal
logic at the heart of a ‘scientific’ philosophy. But a myopia has
settled over our work in the intervening years.
We have retained
much of Russell’s scientific methodology. Philosophical careers stand or
fall now on the subtlety of one’s logical distinctions, or on the
cleverness of the moves one makes on carefully circumscribed, technical
matters. That kind of work is perfectly fine. But we have lost sight of
the political rationale for laying out the rules of the
philosophical game in the way Russell did, with an appeal to logic as an
international language, and a standard of truth that is ‘the same in
England, France, and Germany, in Russia and in Austria’.
What
spectacles can help us correct our philosophical myopia? I suggest that
historical reflection itself can play a salutary role. Unfortunately,
history of philosophy has lately been under attack, so I will close with
a few remarks on its utility.
In a widely discussed recent blog post
attacking the history of philosophy as a useless undertaking, Michael
Huemer of the University of Colorado Boulder tells us about the good kind of philosophy he thinks historians fail to produce:
[L]et’s
suppose that you have a really good historian of philosophy, who does a
really great piece of work by the standards of the field, which also is
completely correct and persuasive. What is the most that can have been
accomplished?
Answer: ‘Now we know what
philosopher P meant by utterance U.’ Before that, maybe some people
thought that U meant X; now we know that it meant Y.
This is of no philosophical import. We still don’t know whether X or Y is true.
Notice that this particular way of construing philosophy’s real job, as the evaluation of whether timeless theses are true, plain and simple, has not been universally shared. Certainly it was not Bosanquet’s view.
The
metaphilosophy Huemer expresses is widely accepted today, and it is a
descendant of Russell’s. But Russell’s view was different. He thought
history of philosophy was valuable in itself, and made influential
contributions in this area; and he thought even technical philosophy can
be assessed in terms of its social and political consequences, which we
get a grip on precisely by looking at history (a point Eric Schliesser
has been exploring). So why did analytic philosophy modify its
methodology over the years? That is a historical question, and one
Huemer would have us pass over in silence, apparently, because ‘history
of philosophy isn’t history or philosophy.’ But without answering this
question, one should not feel confident in seeing Huemer’s
metaphilosophy, popular as it is today, as inevitable.
Huemer
aside, the lesson of my discussion isn’t that we should simply imitate
Russell’s old project more faithfully. Today’s nationalist menace isn’t
your grandmother’s. But Russell was right that even technical philosophy
has political consequences, as Russell was keen to emphasise, and his
unique way of embedding philosophical practice in a larger struggle
against the bloodthirsty, against the war-mongers, against those who
would ‘diminish loving kindness between nations’, is worth studying in
its own context. Maybe we can learn something. For historical reflection
stands to loosen hackneyed assumptions about what philosophical
reflection is or can be. It stands to knock back the toxic complacency
that says that philosophy inevitably must be, always has been, or can’t
help but be, politically quiet.